Volume 46, Issue 3 pp. 377-386
Full Access

‘Alas Poor Hicks’, Indeed! Sixty Years of Use and Abuse—Commentary on Bromwich et al.

FRANK L. CLARKE

Corresponding Author

FRANK L. CLARKE

The University of Newcastle, and The University of Sydney

Frank L. Clarke ([email protected]) is an Emeritus Professor of Accounting, The University of Newcastle, and Honorary Professor of Accounting in the Faculty of Economics and Business, The University of Sydney.Search for more papers by this author
First published: 25 August 2010
Citations: 3

Alas indeed! We might well wonder whether Professor Ray Chambers (1976) would have had the same reservations about using ‘Alas poor Hicks’ to describe what he perceived to be the ‘carelessness and indifference . . . [of] . . . so many . . . who clutched [so] indiscriminately at [Hicks' notion of income]’ had he experienced the matters which Bromwich et al. (2010) explain in their ‘Hicksian Income . . .’ in this issue. In a recently discovered 1976 letter to Sir John Hicks (reproduced as an appendix to this comment—and to which there is no evidence in the Chambers Archive of any reply by Hicks) Ray Chambers commented on accountants' cavalier treatment of Hicks on Income, treatment similar to that by the IASB and FASB of which Bromwich et al. now rightly complain.

Chambers asks Hicks whether his own system of Continuously Contemporary Accounting was what Hicks had in mind with his No. 3 ex post interpretation of his central meaning of income (as outlined in Hicks, 1946). We should bear in mind that Chambers wrote against the background of the Sandilands Committee (1975) selectively using ex ante approximations of Hicks' central meaning to support their adoption of deprival value to underpin their recommendations on how to ‘account for inflation’, and most importantly Sandilands' expropriation of the initialism ‘CCA’ (which Chambers previously had used publicly for several years to describe his Continuously Contemporary Accounting) for their preferred method.

Unaware of that letter, but fully aware of the 1970s setting in which it was written, in Clarke (1988) I made observations regarding the treatment of Hicks by accountants in the thirty years from 1950 to 1980, similar to those of which Chambers complained then and of which Bromwich et al. now complain. These complaints were directed toward unmasking those who did not appear to have read the original. Many appear to have relied on secondary sources to Hicks as a strong, though spurious, ‘authoritative’ support for various asset valuation bases. Appealing to the authority of Hicks' status as a leading economist seems to have been underpinning cases for replacement cost and deprival value asset valuations being promoted strongly at the time by Sandilands and others. The objection lay primarily in what appeared at the time to be resting upon poor research—mainly secondary sources and in many instances selectivity and misquotation. Now, nearly thirty years later, Bromwich et al. find and aptly dismantle the argument of those who, using the same tactics complained of three decades back, are trying to fit Hicks into their preferred valuation method as part of the IASB and FASB Conceptual Framework exercise. Interestingly now, deprival value hardly rates a mention as the preferred measurement base under the ‘fair value’ regime (IASB, 28 May 2009). Bromwich et al. douse with considerable cold water any proposition that Hicks offers support for the IASB/FASB CF preference.

Bromwich et al. complain of the IASB/FASB cherry-picking, being selective, the product of misunderstanding and misapplying those parts of Hicks' exposition that best suit the standard setter. They mount a solid case. And neither the IASB nor the FASB is alone in its cherry-picking. Previous recourse to the ‘Hicksian income’ notion exhibited equal selectivity, misquoting, clumsiness and inaccuracy. Importantly, some (see Clarke, 1988, especially Table 1) referred to only (or predominantly) Hicks' central meaning—that income ought to be thought of as the amount an individual can consume and expect to be as well off at the end of a week as he was at its beginning. Others appealed to his ex ante approximations, some to his ex post approximations and a few vaguely to the entire exposition, namely to ‘Hicks (1946, pp. 171–8)’.

Table 1.
EXAMPLES OF THE 1950–80 PATTERN OF REFERENCING TO HICKS' DISCUSSION OF INCOME IN VALUE AND CAPITALa
Reference to the ‘central meaning’ implied by, e.g., ‘Hicks . . . p. 172’, etc. Reference or allusion to ‘corporate idiom’ extrapolation of the ‘central meaning’ Specific reference to ex ante approximations Specific reference to ex post approximations Vague reference to whole chapter, e.g., ‘Hicks. . . .  pp. 171–8’
Alexander (1950) Alexander (1950)
Edwards (1954)
Johnson (1954) Johnson (1954)
Mathews (1956)
Gordon (1960)
Hendriksen (1961)
Solomons (1961) Solomons (1961)
Edwards and Bell (1961) Edwards and Bell (1961)
Solomons (1962) Solomons (1962)
Hendriksen (1965)
Kerr (1965)
Backer and Bell (1966)
Gynther (1966)
Shwayder (1967)
Hendriksen (1970)
Stamp (1971) Stamp (1971)
Lee (1973) Revsine (1973)
Barton (1974) Barton (1974)
Macdonald (1974) Macdonald (1974) Macdonald (1974)
Mathews Report (1975) Mathews Report (1975)
Sandilands Report (1975) Sandilands Report (1975)
Baxter (1975)
Largay and Livingstone (1975)
Corporate Report (1975) Corporate Report (1975)
Richardson Report (1976) Richardson Report (1976)
Hendriksen (1977)
Most (1977)
Ontario Report (1977) Ontario Report (1977)
Scapens (1977)
Norby (1979)
Ingberman (1980)

Why Hicks' definition of income should have received such acclamation or have been addressed in such a clumsy way in the past is problematic; why it continues to attract such treatment perhaps less so. Hicks had some association with accountants' ruminations—between 1945 and 1951, for example, he sat on the Joint Exploratory Committee sponsored by the Institute of Chartered Accountants in England and Wales and the National Institute of Economic and Social Research. There, we might imagine that he possibly discussed accountants' income with F. Sewell Bray (1949)—though Bray's own later references were only to Hicks' central meaning. But it seems that Hicks knew little of what accountants were about—Brief (1982) drew attention to how little attention Hicks paid to accounting—and that his central meaning had ‘breadth but little depth’. Selectivity, poor analysis, and the disservice it did to him as a modern Austrian School member were salient features of the appeal to Hicks thirty years ago.

Alexander's 1950 Five Monographs on Business Income emerges as the most likely entry of Hicks' income into the mainstream English-language accounting literature. That appears to have provided an initial impetus for selective discussion and reference to Value and Capital. There, Alexander (p. 15) seeded the idea that corporate income may be defined as the increment in its well-offness during an accounting period—‘the amount a corporation can distribute . . . and be as well-off at the end of a year as at the beginning’ (emphasis added).

Table 1 illustrates the higgledy-piggledy references in the accounting literature to Hicks' income over the next thirty years. Notable is the difference there between the function served by that thirty-odd years' fixation by accounting writers on Hicks' exposition and that which Hicks attributed to it in his Value and Capital. For Hicks his thoughts were merely procedural, a step toward gaining a better understanding of the rough approximations that a businessman might use in steering himself through the bewildering situation that may confront him (p. 172). It is to be noted they are rough approximations to a central meaning, not logical categories. Arguably for Hicks these were immature, tentative, experimental notions. He unmistakably floated his central meaning, but it lacked operational finesse. From a pedagogical perspective it was bankrupt. The individual could consume what? How were expectations of an individual in relation to future consumption to be operationalized? And what was the well-offness to which Hicks referred?

Why Hicks should have attracted so much specialized attention is puzzling. Prior to Hicks there is an extensive discussion of income in, or translated into, English. Perhaps it has something to do with those economists favouring what might loosely be regarded to be a concept closer to supporting the idea of income being an overall increase in general purchasing power contradicting the push for replacement price or reproduction cost that found favour in many of those up to 1980 pushing Hicks' ex ante approximations, including Sandilands.

In doing so the selectivity and misquoting in the latest Conceptual Framework exercise that Bromwich et al. properly complain of was rife at the time. The integrity of the sources was a methodological issue then of mammoth proportions. Appeals to Hicks almost universally underpinned cases for current cost accounting entailing the valuation of physical assets at replacement price or reproduction cost. Possibly the present liking for fair value provides the current motivation.

Strong evidence of secondary referencing ought to be noted too, if only to add predictive force to the likelihood of the referencing pattern having been a contributing factor in the development of Anglo-American ideas on accounting income.

Instances of imprecision and misinterpretation in accountants' referencing of Hicks were common. Imprecision in the widely used texts was likely to have far-reaching pedagogic consequences. In Australia at the time, for instance, Henderson and Peirson (1975) was a case in point. In the US, there was Hendriksen's persistent misquotation of Hicks in successive editions of his Accounting Theory. In the 1961 Price Level book and in the 1965 first edition of Accounting Theory (p. 103), Hendriksen ‘quoted’ Hicks as having stated: ‘income is the amount that a person can consume . . . and be as well off at the end’ (emphasis added).

In consequence of the reference being to ‘J. R. Hicks, Value and Capital . . . p. 172’, doubtless Hendriksen was referring there to Hicks' central meaning. At no point, however, in either his central meaning or in any of the approximations to it, did Hicks state ‘and be as well off’ . . . it was ‘and still expect to be as well off’ in each. Hendriksen's version certainly contradicted Hicks' stated proposition at that point. Hicks was unequivocal regarding his ‘and still expect to be’ in all seven versions of income in Value and Capital. Hendriksen repeated the misquotation in his following editions of Accounting Theory (1970, p. 131; 1977, p. 146; 1982, p. 143). Although the educational consequences of successive generations of accounting students being misled in that fashion cannot be evaluated quantitatively, it might reasonably be considered very likely to be far reaching. It is not difficult to contemplate the implications. Gynther (1966, p. 69), for example, declared ‘Hendriksen (1961)’ the declared source of his reference to Hicks in his own frequently made case for replacement price accounting. It is unlikely that there would be much argument that Accounting Theory was a widely used text in English-speaking countries then, and later.

Secondary sourcing by some of those listed in Table 1 reinforces that pattern: for example, the references to Alexander's 1950 recourse to Hicks by Solomons (1961), Edwards and Bell (1961), Backer and Bell (1966), Shwayder (1967) and Revsine (1973). Shwayder (1967) and Barton (1974) had referred to Solomons' 1961 discussion of income; Stamp (1971) referred to Wright (1970) who had referred to Solomons, to Shwayder (1967) and to Alexander (1950). In turn, the Sandilands Committee drew upon Stamp (1971) for support and both the Richardson Report (1976) and the Ontario Report (1977) referred to the Sandilands Committee's 1975 deliberations on the matter. Shwayder (1967, p. 23) referring to the ‘Hicks . . . p. 172’ noted that Goldberg (1965) had reported Hicks' (1946, p. 176) doubt about whether his concept of income was a ‘will-o'-the-wisp’. But Goldberg had referred to No. 2 ex ante in that context, not the central meaning. In further contrast, Hicks had those doubts regarding each of his ex ante notions. His doubt was the motivation for devising the ex post definitions. Revsine's observation (1981, p. 348) caps the secondary referencing with his implication that following Edwards and Bell (1961), virtually everyone referred to them. Backer and Bell (1966) drawing upon Value and Capital was another instance. Through the use of quotation marks, they implied that Hicks had declared (supposedly at p. 180) that the concept of income was unsuitable for ‘advanced theoretical analysis’. The words, in fact, originated in Alexander's paraphrasing of Hicks' explanation that the ex ante approximations were of little use in allaying the ‘peril’ to which ‘positive theoretical economists’ were exposed when using notions and calculations of individuals' incomes. The words were Alexander's, not Hicks'.

Of course, a substantial web of referencing is to be expected in the academic and practitioner attempts to account for price and price-level changes in a literature as voluminous as that dealing with the varied notions of income. But, bearing in mind the importance at the time of the authority drawn from Hicks being such an important feature of the case for CCA, it is significant that early instances of clear misinterpretation and omission went unchecked at the time. Significantly, now they are being unashamedly repeated.

Perhaps, a defensible inference is that the readily available Value and Capital was not directly referred to as much as it ought to have been because of the academic status of many of those in the referencing loop. But, the repetitive, unqualified, selective references to Value and Capital evoke a strong inference that virtually no recourse has been had to Hicks' complementary works. Bromwich et al. are clearly of this mind regarding the current offenders.

There also was a tendency for authors to quote the central meaning (or to imply it by making a sole reference to ‘Value and Capital, p. 172’) and then reword it, supposedly so as to apply to a corporation rather than an individual. That Alexander (1950) appears to have been one of the first was noted above. Curiously, Alexander had not referred to Hicks by name up to that point, but had just previously noted that ‘an individual's income’ might be thought of in terms similar to Hicks' ex ante notions (pp. 13–15). His only reference to Hicks came on page 74. That discussion suggests that his modification to slot into a ‘corporate context’ ought to have had ‘expect to be’ inserted immediately before ‘as well off’, in a manner similar to Hicks' ex ante No. 2 approximation. In the wash-up, Alexander's words or their import were used by others subsequently to give Hicks' central meaning its corporate persona.

A similar flow-on consequence is applicable to Alexander's extrapolation of Hicks' central meaning to a ‘corporate’ setting. Arguably, its spread was wide: by Johnson (1954) in the United States, for example; by Stamp (1971) in the United Kingdom; the Sandilands Committee Report (Inflation Accounting, 1975, para. 98); in the Corporate Report (of which Stamp was one of the authors) (1976), and Scapens (1977); in Australia by the Mathews Committee enquiring into Inflation and Taxation (Report of the Committee of Enquiry Into Inflation and Taxation, 1975, p. 398); ‘from’ Australia, by Barton in The Accounting Review (1974); in the Report of the Committee of Enquiry Into Inflation Accounting (1976) chaired by Justice Richardson, in New Zealand; and in Canada by the Ontario Committee of Inflation Accounting (1977). In each ‘expect to be as well off’ (or similar words) have been substituted for Alexander's ‘be as well off’.

The Richardson Committee (1976) was representative of the prevailing view: ‘We are satisfied that this concept is the only valid general approach to the problem of the definition of profit’ (paras 4.02–4.04). Only Stamp (1971) within that group explained ‘how’ Hicks' central meaning could be translated into the ‘distribute . . . and expect to be as well-off’ format. A connection between the translated ‘distribute’ and the central meaning's notion of ‘consume’ was not apparent. No specific ex ante approximations were referred to for support. Yet by the inclusion of ‘spend . . . and expect to be able to spend’ No. 2 ex ante would appear to have been closer to the idea of a ‘corporate distribution’ than the central notion per se. By specifying ‘expect to be able to pay the same dividends in each ensuing year’, explaining that such ‘is equivalent to Income No. 2 in Hicks’, Barton (1974) appeared to have followed that reasoning.

Earlier, others had referred to Hicks' ex ante notions, but not to his ex post definitions. A general reference by Edwards and Bell (1961) only to ‘Hicks pp. 171–188’ by implication implied that they had rejected, missed or ignored his ex post approximations. They were pursuing support for the possibility of measuring income through a comparison of ‘subjective values’ at the beginning and end of each period, based upon what ‘managers expect to earn on the firm's existing net assets’ (p. 25). Yet ‘pp. 171–188’ of Value and Capital comprises the entire Chapter XIV on ‘Income’; from the foot of page 178 to 181 Hicks' exposition deals almost exclusively with extensions of his central meaning to his ex post approximations.

Revsine (1973) had also referred to the entirety of Hicks' Chapter XIV for illustration and support of notions of ‘expected income’ and ‘unexpected income’ (p. 96). ‘Unexpected income’ is possibly similar to the ‘windfall’ gains and losses Hicks tried to have his ex post definitions capture. If, as he later (pp. 101–4) implied, at that point by ‘economic income’ Revsine is referring to ‘replacement price income’, arguably his reference might more correctly have been only to Hicks' ex ante approximations. Revsine's explanation that the ‘unexpected income component of economic income . . . develops as a result of changes in expectations’ (pp. 96–7) was a purely ex ante notion. Hicks' ‘windfalls’ by contrast were the differences between what was ‘expected’ and what was ‘realized’ (p. 178).

Alas, Indeed!

We are unaware whether Hicks replied to Chambers' 1976 query, which primarily centred on a possible verification that he understood Hicks' intentions correctly. There is no response letter in the Chambers Archive. Chambers' contention was that it was Hicks' ex post Income No. 3 that was needed to operationalize accounting in a corporate setting. However, we should note that Chambers was not suggesting Hicks favoured the former's CoCoA mode of accounting so much as that CoCoA aligned with Hicks' depiction of the No. 3 ex post approximation to his central meaning of income. We might imagine that had a confirmation been forthcoming from Hicks, Chambers would have remained confident to argue that accounting should conform to CoCoA, irrespective of whether Hicks appeared confident that any of his income depictions were suitable for decision making—the point that Bromwich et al. pursue. We know from Hicks (1979) that he had not anticipated that accountants would strive, some diligently, but so many carelessly, so cavalier-like, and continue to do so as now Bromwich et al. so aptly show.

And whereas knowing what Hicks might have replied to Chambers would be fascinating, perhaps we might content ourselves with what we can safely salvage from ‘Hicksian income’. Bromwich et al. note (p. 355), ‘Hicks does not find a satisfactory, practical way of defining a business firm's income that could be used in accounting, whether ex ante or ex post’.

Unquestionably Hicks' central meaning of income struck a chord with Alexander sixty years ago. Perhaps that broad central meaning of income and particularly the capital maintenance idea which accountants grasped thereafter is what we should be contented to take from Hicks.

Unquestionably, the use and abuse of his contribution to economic theory in the manner accountants have employed over (at least) the past sixty years should stop.

Appendices

Appendix

Department of Accounting

14 April 1976

Sir John Hicks

Research School of Social Sciences

Australian National University

CANBERRA ACT 2600

Dear Sir John

For many years some parts of Chapter XIV of your Value and Capital[1939] have been quoted and requoted as grounds for an ‘ideal’ notion of income, a notion which accountants in the ordinary course of affairs should adopt, or seek to approximate, for business purposes. The parts are the description of the ‘central criterion’, in the lower part of p. 172 and the first sentence of section 6 on p. 176 of the Second Edition.

As the words of these passages indicate, and as you indicate quite clearly on p. 178, the notion you were dealing with is a notion of income ex ante. It is the function of accountants to calculate income ex post, however. You may find it curious that an ex ante notion should be adopted as a pattern for an ex post calculation. But more curious is the fact that, in the literature which comes under my notice (the theoretical literature of accounting), very few seem to be aware that you alluded to a series of ex post definitions corresponding with Incomes No. 1, No. 2 and No. 3 ex ante. Further, your central criterion has become described, quite frequently, as ‘the economist's concept of income’ and the ‘Hicksian concept of income’, as if it were the only concept, ex ante or ex post!

The carelessness and indifference which these widespread misapprehensions represent have induced the wish to write a critical note under the caption ‘Alas, Poor Hicks!’ But I fear that may prompt some to think too literally of the setting of Hamlet's words—and I would not wish that. I write presently, however, to ask if you would clarify a matter.

You described Income No. 1 ex post as equal to Consumption plus Capital accumulation—‘an objective magnitude’ (179), since ‘the capital value of the individual's property’ at the beginning of the week (and also at the end) is an assessable figure. The treatment of Income No. 1 ex ante refers to ‘maintaining intact the capital value of prospective receipts’ (173). A capitalized value of prospective receipts is of course entirely subjective. I presume therefore that when reference is made to the ‘capital value of the individual's property’ you cannot mean a capitalized value of prospective receipts, and that you mean the money value or money equivalent of the property, at the beginning or end of the week as the case may be. These money equivalents (or resale prices) would be objective in the sense that they are discovered by observation, not invented by cerebration.

Income No. 1 ex post was selected for special mention (p. 178). But having developed Income No. 3 ex ante to deal with spending in real terms, it seems to me that Income No. 3 ex post would be the most general and inclusive notion, for such purposes as people use knowledge of income ex post, either for particular individuals or firms or the community as a whole. Especially does this seem to be the case when over the last couple of decades, the divergence between money income and ‘real’ income has been so marked.

On such notions as these, I have constructed a method of calculating income ex post as follows:

Let £0N0, £1N1 represent the money equivalents of the net assets of a firm at t0, t1 respectively.

Let p1 represent the proportionate change in an index of the general level of prices between t0 and t1; so that, in real terms,

£01 (1 + p)

Let Y1 represent income of the period t0 to t1

Then Y11N1−£0N0

 =£1N1−£1(1 + p)N0

or £1Y11 (N1− N0− pN0)

The money equivalents of assets at any date, t, are observed resale prices. They are homogeneous and therefore agreeable. The amounts of the liabilities of the firm are known at any such date, and may properly be deducted from the total of the money equivalents of the assets. The difference is the amount of the net assets at any date. As it is a number of ‘dated pounds’, an index or a proportionate change in an index may properly be applied to it, to obtain a differently dated ‘real terms’ equivalent.

Since N0 and N1 are found by observation, (N1− N0) embraces net revenues and the effects of all changes in the structure of prices which have fallen on the firm in the interval. Since borrowings are hedges against losses in general purchasing power through asset holdings in an inflationary period, the firm is affected adversely only to the extent of N0. The amount of the adverse effect is £1pN0. £1Y1 thus is inclusive of the effects of all gains from trade, of all rises and falls (in the period) in the money prices of assets of the firm during their holding, of the debt of the firm, and of the change in the general level of prices (or the general purchasing power of money).

It seems to me that income ex post, so calculated, would be a far better basis for comparisons and aggregations than the products of the vagrant, ad hoc, calculations now common in commercial practice. It seems that the resulting income figure would serve wage, price and other negotiations far more fairly than current practices. It seems that the income figure would be an entirely neutral base for taxation of business incomes; since it would make no special imposts or concessions in respect of particular forms of assets or types of increment, though at the same time it would make proper and properly calculable allowance for the effects of shifts in the general level of prices. I wonder if you would agree that this method of calculation tallies with what you proposed as Income No. 3 ex post.

I am aware that Value and Capital was directed to a problem in an entirely different field of discourse from the microcosmic field of business accounting. It concerns me that so many who have clutched at it for the latter purpose have clutched indiscriminately. The most recent instance occurs in the Sandilands Report on Inflation Accounting of September last year. On the other hand, I have taken some comfort from what seems to me to be substantial correspondence between your notion of income ex post and my proposal for deriving its magnitude. I wonder whether that comfort is properly taken.

My concern with the whole matter stems from the increased usage of business accounts for a whole range of purposes in the last thirty years. To the extent that national income and sectoral statistics rely on business accounts, they are less than satisfactory, in spite of attempts to ‘correct’ the raw data for imperfections in accounting processes. For all the negotiations and exploratory calculations associated with the regulation of prices, wages, competition, tariffs, taxes, the money supply, and so on, the present mode of calculating business income provides a much less satisfactory basis than the importance of these matters warrants. And I strongly suspect that a great deal of the academic analysis and public debate which turns on reports of business income and the aggregate investment in the business sector from time to time is poorly founded because of the serious limitations of current accounting practice. To do something to rectify this has been the object of much of my own work for many years.

Sincerely

R. J. Chambers

Footnotes
  • 1 This comment draws from previously published work by the author (Clarke, 1982, 1988). ‘Alas poor Hicks’ is taken from the 1976 letter by Chambers to Hicks, see appendix to this comment. That letter was found in the Chambers Archive, USA P202.
  • 2 For actual extracts on income from these and other contemporary sources see Chambers (1995, especially ss 160–5).
  • 3 Sourced from the R. J. Chambers Collection, University of Sydney Archives Unit, USA P202.
    • The full text of this article hosted at iucr.org is unavailable due to technical difficulties.